Free trade is anti-property rights

In the comments, PG constructed an interesting and effective logical argument against free trade, which I have organized thusly:

1. Free traders insist upon the existence of property rights and the sovereign exercise of those rights as axiomatic. From this foundation, they argue that all actions concerning with whom one will trade, regardless of their location or nation, are protected by those property rights and cannot be morally infringed.

2. If a group of people happen to share the rights to a property in an ownership group, they must decide together on how those rights are exercised. No single individual can sell the property or permit its use by others without the agreement of the other rights holders. The ownership group collectively has the right to decide who and what are permitted to enter their property. It is not an infringement of any one owner’s property right if the greater part of the ownership group does not wish to sell the property or to permit entry to certain parties or items.

3. A nation is a group of people who share a common property that is delineated by the national borders. This group of people must therefore decide in some consensus manner how the rights to that property are exercised. They can therefore decide who and what are permitted to enter the national property in precisely the same manner that a house-owning group decide who and what are permitted to enter their house. It is not an infringement of any one individual’s property right if the greater part of the nation does not wish to sell the land possessed by the nation or permit entry to certain parties or items.

4. To deny a nation the property right to enact tariffs or refuse permission for goods, capital, or labor to cross its borders, is tantamount to either denying a) property rights or b) the nation’s existence.

5. However, denying the existence of nations is not only empirically false, it creates a logical contradiction for the free trader because it requires denying the individual property-owner the right to form collective property-ownership groups from which nations are made. The free trade position depends upon the idea that individuals possess property rights, but groups of more than one individual cannot.

6. Therefore, free trade doctrine requires the denial of the very property rights upon which it is founded. As PG correctly concludes, “their whole argument is an outright logical contradiction”.

As evidence in support of PG’s logical construction, I offer the following statements concerning the existence of nations from two champions of the dogma, Mr. Gary North and our own Unger.

North: “Defenders of tariffs present themselves as defenders of the nation, when in fact the nation, from the point of view of economics, is not a collective entity. The nation, from an economic standpoint, is simply a convenient name that we give to people inside invisible judicial lines known as national borders.”

Unger: “I do not consider myself an ‘American’, except as a verbal convenience, or have any care at all for ‘America’.”

Now, it can certainly be pointed out that the mere existence of a nation does not mean that all of its members are voluntary members of it and it cannot be denied that the legitimate property rights of the nation can be abused or ignored just as they are in the case of individual property rights. But PG’s logic suffices to demonstrate that the property rights argument upon which many free traders heavily rely is far from the conclusive one that they believe it to be.


Mailvox: the Hazlitt international trade challenge III

In which my critique of Chapter 11 of Henry Hazlitt’s Economics in One Lesson is completed. It has been just over a year since I wrote the first two parts of it, so if your memory requires refreshing, you may find it helpful to refer to part one and part two of the critique. In order to make the errors in his argument easier to locate when reading my explications of them, I have taken the liberty of identifiying them with numbers (N) in the text.

In concluding his chapter on free trade, Hazlitt writes: For the erection of tariff walls has the same effect as the erection of real walls. It is significant that the protectionists habitually use the language of warfare. They talk of “repelling an invasion” of foreign products. And the means they suggest in the fiscal field are like those of the battlefield. The tariff barriers that are put up to repel this invasion are like the tank traps, trenches and barbed-wire entanglements created to repel or slow down attempted invasion by a foreign army.(1)

And just as the foreign army is compelled to employ more expensive means to surmount those obstacles — bigger tanks, mine detectors, engineer corps to cut wires, ford streams and build bridges—so more expensive and efficient transportation means must be developed to surmount tariff obstacles. On the one hand, we try to reduce the cost of transportation between England and America, or Canada and the United States, by developing faster and more efficient planes and ships, better roads and bridges, better locomotives and motor trucks. On the other hand, we offset this investment in efficient transportation by a tariff that makes it commercially even more difficult to transport goods than it was before. We make it a dollar cheaper to ship the sweaters, and then increase the tariff by two dollars to prevent the sweaters from being shipped. By reducing the freight that can be profitably carried, we reduce the value of the investment in transport efficiency.

The tariff has been described as a means of benefiting the producer at the expense of the consumer. In a sense this is correct. Those who favor it think only of the interests of the producers immediately benefited by the particular duties involved. They forget the interests of the consumers who are immediately injured by being forced to pay these duties. But it is wrong to think of the tariff issue as if it represented a conflict between the interests of producers as a unit against those of consumers as a unit. It is true that the tariff hurts all consumers as such.(2) It is not true that it benefits all producers as such. On the contrary, as we have just seen, it helps the protected producers at the expense of all other American producers, and particularly of those who have a comparatively large potential export market. We can perhaps make this last point clearer by an exaggerated example. Suppose we make our tariff wall so high that it becomes absolutely prohibitive, and no imports come in from the outside world at all. Suppose, as a result of this, that the price of sweaters in America goes up only $5. Then American consumers, because they have to pay $5 more for a sweater, will spend on the average five cents less in each of a hundred other American industries.(3) (The figures are chosen merely to illustrate a principle: there will, of course, be no such symmetrical distribution of the loss; moreover, the sweater industry itself will doubtless be hurt because of protection of still other industries. But these complications may be put aside for the moment.)

Now because foreign industries will find their market in America totally cut off, they will get no dollar exchange, and therefore they will be unable to buy any American goods at all.(4) As a result of this, American industries will suffer in direct proportion to the percentage of their sales previously made abroad.(5) Those that will be most injured, in the first instance, will be such industries as raw cotton producers, copper producers, makers of sewing machines, agricultural machinery, typewriters, commercial airplanes, and so on.

A higher tariff wall, which, however, is not prohibitive, will produce the same kind of results as this, but merely to a smaller degree.

The effect of a tariff, therefore, is to change the structure of American production. It changes the number of occupations, the kind of occupations, and the relative size of one industry as compared with another. It makes the industries in which we are comparatively inefficient larger, and the industries in which we are comparatively efficient smaller. Its net effect, therefore, is to reduce American efficiency, as well as to reduce efficiency in the countries with which we would otherwise have traded more largely.
In the long run, notwithstanding the mountains of argument pro and con, a tariff is irrelevant to the question of employment.(6) (True, sudden changes in the tariff, either upward or downward, can create temporary unemployment, as they force corresponding changes in the structure of production. Such sudden changes can even cause a depression.) But a tariff is not irrelevant to the question of wages. In the long run it always reduces real wages, because it reduces efficiency, production and wealth.(7)
Thus all the chief tariff fallacies stem from the central fallacy with which this book is concerned. They are the result of looking only at the immediate effects of a single tariff rate on one group of producers, and forgetting the long-run effects both on consumers as a whole and on all other producers.(8)

(I hear some reader asking: “Why not solve this by giving tariff protection to all producers?” But the fallacy here is that this cannot help producers uniformly, and cannot help at all domestic producers who already “outsell” foreign producers: these efficient producers must necessarily suffer from the diversion of purchasing power brought about by the tariff.)

On the subject of the tariff we must keep in mind one final precaution. It is the same precaution that we found necessary in examining the effects of machinery. It is useless to deny that a tariff does benefit—or at least can benefit—special interests. True, it benefits them at the expense of every one else. But it does benefit them. If one industry alone could get protection, while its owners and workers enjoyed the benefits of free trade in everything else they bought, that industry would benefit, even on net balance. As an attempt is made to extend the tariff blessings, however, even people in the protected industries, both as producers and consumers, begin to suffer from other people’s protection, and may finally be worse off even on net balance than if neither they nor anybody else had protection.(9)

But we should not deny, as enthusiastic free traders have so often done, the possibility of these tariff benefits to special groups. We should not pretend, for example, that a reduction of the tariff would help everybody and hurt nobody. It is true that its reduction would help the country on net balance. But somebody would be hurt. Groups previously enjoying high protection would be hurt. That in fact is one reason why it is not good to bring such protected interests into existence in the first place. But clarity and candor of thinking compel us to see and acknowledge that some industries are right when they say that a removal of the tariff on their product would throw them out of business and throw their workers (at least temporarily) out of jobs. And if their workers have developed specialized skills, they may even suffer permanently, or until they have at long last learnt equal skills. In tracing the effects of tariffs, as in tracing the effects of machinery, we should endeavor to see all the chief effects, in both the short run and the long run, on all groups.

As a postscript to this chapter I should add that its argument is not directed against all tariffs, including duties collected mainly for revenue, or to keep alive industries needed for war; nor is it directed against all arguments for tariffs. It is merely directed against the fallacy that a tariff on net balance “provides employment,” “raises wages,” or “protects the American standard of living.” It does none of these things; and so far as wages and the standard of living are concerned, it does the precise opposite.(10) But an examination of duties imposed for other purposes would carry us beyond our present subject. Nor need we here examine the effect of import quotas, exchange controls, bilateralism and other means of reducing, diverting or preventing international trade. Such devices have, in general, the same effects as high or prohibitive tariffs, and often worse effects. They present more complicated issues, but their net results can be traced through the same kind of reasoning that we have just applied to tariff barriers.

In this third section of the chapter, Hazlitt commits ten errors while offering the observant reader a foreshadowing of anti-free trade arguments to come. Indeed, in his careless failure to think through some of his own statements, he very nearly lays the groundwork for some of the more effective modern arguments against free trade.

1. Hazlitt fails to realize that the reason for the habitual use of the language of warfare by protectionists is because free trade in its labor and services aspect is a literal form of invasion. The Mexican invasion of the United States is ten times larger in scope than Operation Barbarossa, and especially in a quasi-democracy where voting rights are quickly and readily granted, a free trade-led invasion and occupation will lead to the political subjugation of the invaded that will last longer and can be more oppressive than an actual military occupation. Most of the 3.9 million Axis soldiers who invaded the Soviet Union in 1941 never fired a shot and the only substantive difference between a military invasion and a labor invasion is the failure to react by the government of the invaded nation. Support for this statement can be seen in the way defenders of immigration claim these peaceful immigrants will not leave the invaded nation without the use of lethal state-sanctioned violence.

2. Hazlitt correctly notes that it is wrong to consider the effects of a tariff from a crude perspective that lumps all producers and consumers into separate units of competing interests. But he is manifestly wrong to claim that tariffs harm all consumers, because consumers are also workers and the small cost of the tariff to the consumer-worker is more than mitigated by its benefit to him. The root of his error here is revealed in a subsequent error.

3. Here Hazlitt ironically forgets that as a champion of free trade, he cannot assume an increased tariffprice of $5 on sweaters means five cents less spent on 100 other American products. Since imports previously represented 17.3 percent of GDP, the increased $5 tariffprice actually means about 4.14 cents less spent on other American products. Since he also leaves debt and savings out of the equation, it is entirely possible that the imposition of a ban on imports will not shift the domestic consumption pattern in the way he envisions. And finally, he also ignores the law of supply and demand, which suggests that the increased price will reduce the demand for sweaters, thereby indicating no net effect on other American goods at all.

4. This is a massive and major blunder. Perhaps it is not Hazlitt’s fault that he didn’t understand the global reserve currency effect at the time he was writing his book in 1946, (although as an advocate of the gold standard, he should have at least been aware of the obvious implications), but that doesn’t change the fact that his conclusion is simply false. Barring retaliatory protectionist measures that actually ban the purchase of American goods, it is absolutely ludicrous to claim that foreigners will be unable to purchase American goods due to a lack of dollar exchange. Forget the trillions in Eurodollars already floating around outside US borders and the hundreds of trillions in derivatives, the creative magnitude of various financial devices means that foreign markets will always be able to acquire American goods even they cannot trade in dollars. This also erroneously assumes that American manufacturers would not accept foreign currencies or debt instruments in exchange for their goods. And if we take the Eurodollars into account, they are the largest source of global finance, accounting for more than 90 percent of international loans according to Wikipedia.

5. Hazlitt’s fifth error in this section follows directly from his fourth. Since American industries will not necessarily suffer at all, they obviously will not suffer in direct proportion to the percentage of their sales previously made abroad.

6. This is a brutal mistake. It is simply laughable, to assert as nakedly as Hazlitt does, that “a tariff is irrelevant to the question of employment”. History has clearly demonstrated is that the effects on employment are not merely temporary ones that result from sudden changes in the tariff, and indeed, the negative long-term effects of free trade on employment has become one of the primary economic arguments for protectionism. Both the logic and the empirical evidence weigh heavily against Hazlitt here.

7. Hazlitt errs when he states that tariffs always reduces real wages because they reduces efficiency, production and wealth. Even if we accept his statements about reducing efficiency, production, and wealth at face value, we have repeatedly seen that it is freer trade, not tariffs, that reduces real wages, because the first-order reduction in the demand for domestic labor outweighs the proposed second-order effects of reductions in efficiency, production, and wealth. It was inexcusable for Hazlitt to miss this, since the shift of production to lower-wage countries is one of the core mechanisms of free trade and is one of the primary causes of capital movement.

8. This is such a monstrously hypocritical statement that it amazes me Hazlitt could have made it. To accuse the advocates of tariffs of “forgetting the long-run effects both on consumers as a whole and on all other producers” might be apt when considering centuries-old arguments against free trade, but simply cannot be reasonably applied in any way to modern critics, whose arguments are very broad-based and primarily focused on the harm to producers brought about be free trade. As those who have followed this ongoing discourse will recognize, it is the protectionists who are looking at the societal effects and the free traders who are not only ignoring them, but openly stating their indifference to them.

9. Hazlitt extends his flawed arguments into the realm of fiction by proposing a fictional scenario where the second- and third-order costs of protectionism outweigh the first-order benefits of having one’s industry protected. It’s not entirely absurd, however, as one can envision the inutility of having a profitable business in a protected market that has grown technologically stagnant. However, in doing so, he neatly anticipates, in reverse, the modern protectionist argument, which points out that the benefits to corporations of sending their capital and labor abroad come at a severe cost to the society in which the shareholders in that corporation have to live, potentially so severe that it will outweigh their greater profits.

10. Hazlitt not only fails to provide any support for his claim that tariffs do not provide employment, raise wages or protect the American standard of living, his claim is demonstrably false in economic, logical and empirical terms. His argument is outdated, is based primarily on naked assertions, and is undermined by more than sixty years of historical evidence directly contradicting the lofty promises of the free trade doctrine he champions here.

Thus concludes my critique of Hazlitt’s argument for free trade, which identifies 23 specific errors in his argument, all of which will have to be defended by the true believers in free trade doctrine without resort to irrelevant tangents such as Mr. North’s uneconomic “guns and badges” defense before it can be appealed to again. Next up: Mises and his defense of free trade as presented in Liberalism.


The Globalist Propositions of Free Trade

If the free-traders cannot understand how one nation can grow rich at the expense of another, we need not wonder, since these same gentlemen also refuse to understand how within one country one class can enrich itself at the expense of another…. But, in general, the protective system of our day is conservative, while the free trade system is destructive. It breaks up old nationalities and pushes the antagonism of the proletariat and the bourgeoisie to the extreme point. In a word, the free trade system hastens the social revolution. It is in this revolutionary sense alone, gentlemen, that I vote in favor of free trade.
On the Question of Free Trade, Karl Marx, 1848

Mises may have never wavered from the view that free trade is a crucial economic policy in the program to restrict the growth of socialism. This does not alter the easily demonstrated fact that Mises was completely wrong on this particular issue, as can be seen by taking the position of Karl Marx into account, or examining the following chart, which shows the very strong statistical correlation, 0.95, between the increasing volume of international trade and the increase in the debt owed by the U.S. federal government.

It doesn’t matter if one prefers to utilize different measures of the expansion of the power of the central state, as they will show much the same result.  What this chart shows is a five-decade refutation of the Misean assertion that an increase in trade intrinsically inhibits the expansion of the scale and scope of state power, and particularly after 1994, it shows that a reduction of protectionism does not reduce the continued growth of the state in the slightest. To the extent that any claim of causation can be made, (and I am not making one here), we must conclude that it is arguments and policies in favor of free trade that “help to expand the power of the state” and “move in the direction of central economic planning.”

This should also not be mistaken for a claim that an increase in international trade, or even an increase in the trade deficit, is responsible for all, or even for most, of the growing amount of public and private debt. That would be impossible, since the $738 million in new debt required to pay for the 2011 balance of payments deficit in goods would barely cover two quarters worth of new federal debt alone, and obviously the federal government is neither purchasing nor financing the purchase of all foreign imports.

Mr. North claims that the central economic issue dividing the right wing movement is the issue of protectionism. This may well be true, I have no opinion on the matter except to say that I believe there is a much stronger right wing case against free trade than can be made for it. After all, the political right generally considers concepts such as national identity, culture, and tradition to be matters of serious and even vital import whereas the political left disdains them, and in some cases even denies their existence. So when Mr. North refers to “invisible lines known as borders”, it should be clear that although he is a man of the right, he is addressing this issue from a distinctly leftward position.

Where Mr. North appears to go fundamentally awry on this issue is his inability to distinguish between the state and the nation. He claims, correctly enough, that the statist equates the state and society and sees the state as the one true agent of the nation. He notes that some statists actually believe that the state is the same as the nation, and this is true. However, although North appears to understand that the state is not the nation, he clearly fails to appreciate that his arguments against the state do not necessarily apply to the nation. Indeed, the use of the term nation-state in a non-ironic manner is to reveal an outdated mindset that fails to recognize the way the laws and goverments of most Western states are openly anti-nationalistic.

North asserts the collectivist begins with the concept of the state as the final authority, while libertarian theory begins with the concept of the individual as the final authority. But as a Christian who claims that his view of economics begins with God as the final authority, North not only shows that he is no libertarian, but should recognize that nations do exist, that they are more than mere invisible lines, and that they are neither states nor individuals. A nation can be a state, but in most cases, nations are spread across two or more states, and many states encompass multiple nations. This adds a complicating factor to North’s case that he simply ignores in his attempt to create a false dichotomy between the libertarian free trader and the protectionist collectivist.

North clearly recognizes he has a problem here, as he acknowledges that conservatives say they don’t equate the state with the nation, but then promptly conflates the two into “the nation-state” before attempting to distract the reader by waving the red herring of mercantilism, which was a coherent historical system that has very little to do with modern protectionism except for also favoring the use of tariffs. He offers nothing but misleading  rhetoric combined with inept logic here, and promptly goes back to complaining about the state again without ever dealing with the legitimate problems raised concerning the material difference between the state and the nation. And in the end, he finally gives up and throws in the towel by attempting to deny the existence of nations.

“There is a true bait-and-switch operation going on here. Defenders of tariffs present themselves as defenders of the nation, when in fact the nation, from the point of view of economics, is not a collective entity. The nation, from an economic standpoint, is simply a convenient name that we give to people inside invisible judicial lines known as national borders.”

But the only bait-and-switch taking place here is by North, who is substituting “nation” for “state” and attempting to hide this by claiming that this substitution is justified “from an economic standpoint”. But the bulk of North’s case and most his complaints about protectionism, such as the oft-repeated “badges and guns” argument, have nothing to do with economics at all. This substitution leads North into a totally false claim about how the “entire concept of protectionism” depends upon a series of propositions that no protectionist needs to hold. North’s simplistic approach simply cannot account for the possibility that anyone might be aware of the potential divergence between the interest of the nation and the interests of the state, and favor the former without promoting the latter. And it is truly ironic that he accuses protectionists of “welfare statism” when his free trade argument amounts to nothing more than international welfare and the distribution of wealth from societies with high living standards to those with lower ones.

Of course, it should not be surprising that in what increasingly appears to be his dotage, North is incapable of grasping complex issues.  He even seems to have completely forgotten that 12 years ago he himself advocated the use of tariffs, with all those terrible badges and guns, in the interests of liberty. He complains that those who start their analysis with the nation and still seek to defend the free market suffer from intellectual schizophrenia and do not know how to think straight, but in doing so, only demonstrates his failure to understand that the nationalist argument includes economic elements but is not limited to them.

I strongly suspect that North’s refusal to recognize the link between free trade and revolutionary globalism identified by Marx is because, as a post-millenialist, he himself is a utopian globalist who favors the destruction of nations. This also explains his callous indifference towards not only the wealth of nations, but even their existence, as like Marx, he anticipates the Worker’s Paradiseliteral Heaven on Earth.

The Globalist Propositions of Free Trade are as follows:

  • The nation does not exist.
  • The state is defined by invisible lines.
  • The individual has no responsibility to anyone beside himself.
  • Everyone has the right to work and live anywhere in the world they want.
  • Free Trade organizations and agreements have nothing to do with free trade, even if they lower tariffs and result in increased international trade.
  • The state does not require funding.
  • All government is unnecessary and illegitimate.

WND column

The Religion of Free Trade

Let us suppose I told you of a certain doctrine in which millions of people believe without ever having read the book in which it is contained, which is predicated upon a situation that has never existed, and promises positive consequences that not only have never been delivered, but we are told cannot even be measured and cannot be realized without achieving something that has never been done before in the history of man. Furthermore, the doctrine was developed by a successful gambler and politician with absolutely no credentials or qualifications on the subject, which he had never even encountered before the age of 27, in tandem with a related theory that is so obviously insane that barely anyone has ever even heard of it.

So long as we are careful to set aside any reliance upon the genetic fallacy, does this sound like a doctrine that is not only infallible, but one that it would be crazy to even consider questioning? And yet, the fervor with which the advocates of the free-trade doctrine defend David Ricardo’s outdated, disproven theory of comparative advantage and decry those who question it is so ferocious as to indicate the nature of a belief that can only be described as religious.


Free trade: the outstanding questions

Since some of you appeared to mistake my very limited offerings on the topic of free trade and Gary North’s defense of it for a complete and comprehensive analysis of the theoretical, moral, practical, and political aspects of the free trade doctrine as well as a coherent Austrian case for US protectionism, I thought it might be useful if the various questions raised by the various free trade supporters were gathered in one place rather than strewn throughout the comments on various posts so that I can be certain to address all of the substantive ones when I do present that coherent, comprehensive, and perhaps even conclusive case.

So, if there is a question from the comments you feel has not yet been answered, (and I am not claiming to have answered them all), or if you have a new question that is related to the subject, please ask it here. I’m not going to be responding to them in the comments, but rather, in the post when I eventually present the anti-free trade case. And please note that I asked for questions, not vacuous, grand-standing assertions claiming “you need to prove X”, as the comment history here suggests the chances are high that there is no need to do anything of the sort.


Mailvox: free trade and automation

JC has a question concerning the different consequences of free trade versus automation:

Interesting discussion on free trade on your blog. Im still going thru the comments on the last one. I have to admit this discussion is all new to me and I have a lot of homework to do to keep up. But I have a question which I shall preface thus:

If for example an American manufacturer moves to another country with lower labor costs, etc., and sells products to American consumers at a lower price than they would have had they stayed in America and hired American workers, the lower priced consumer goods would not really help them since they wouldnt have jobs to take advantage of the lower prices.

I’m thinking this is just the same as a manufacturer deciding to automate production and laying off workers because it’s cheaper to use machines, which is what is happening in America where manufacturing output continues to grow because of American ingenuity in technology but unemployment remains high. It would be like the manufacturer moving the factory overseas because it would be cheaper to produce there. My question is: How is free trade bad, while automation is good in the example I gave above? (I’m assuming you think technological advances in manufacturing is good of course.)

Im looking forward to spending more time over at Vox Popoli. I know you put it up mainly for yourself, but Im sure you are aware that a lot of people are getting a real education reading the posts there and participating in the discussions.

There are several ways that job losses through automation is preferable to job losses through free trade, but JC is right to point out that there are still some material problems presented by it. This is something that has concerned me for some time, and I’ve been contemplating a post about it ever since Chateau Heartiste brought up the issue a few weeks ago.

First, when jobs are lost to automation rather than free trade, the capital and the profits remain in the domestic market. Second, it’s much easier to prevent free trade than technological progress because in the one case the national interest is in line with the domestic producer, in the other it opposes the producers interest. Third, (and this is a consequence of the first thing), the transition of labor from an automated industry to a new one remains viable when the capital and profits remain within the domestic market, otherwise, labor has no choice but to move where the capital investment is taking place.

This is why dishonest advocates of free trade falsely attempt to claim that the free movement of labor is not part of the free trade doctrine. They know that no one will support free trade once the understand that it intrinsically necessitates the large-scale export of their friends, relatives, and neighbors to other markets, and quite possibly their own expatriation. In the case of automation, on the other hand, there is a reasonable expectation that the capital will be reinvested in the domestic market, thereby creating new jobs in that market. That doesn’t mean the process won’t be painful, or as increasingly concerns me, because there is no real productive need for the excess labor, it will be mopped up using a combination of makework private sector jobs, public sector sinecures, and welfare payments.

Of course, in the case of automation, such a solution is possible because the profits have increased and remain within the country. In the case of free trade, not only have the jobs disappeared, but so have the capital and the profits that would pay for either jobs in a new industry as well as the social safety net.


Losing it on free trade

Gary North now demonstrates that he’s not only logically inept, but even appears to be willing to lie about his opponents in defense of his free trade dogma. I found this to be more than a little remarkable since I had previously considered him to be short-sighted and misguided on the topic, as well as rather lazy since he couldn’t be bothered to read the material on which he was commenting, but I never imagined that he would also be intellectually dishonest:

I have found over the years that when I debate with people who promote tariffs, meaning sales taxes on imported goods that are enforced by people with badges and guns, they always adopt arguments that apply only to America’s side of the border. They refuse to adopt those very same arguments for people on the other side of the border.

I challenge defenders of tariffs to state their arguments in terms of both of the people who want to trade, not just the American. The ethics and economics of restricted trade surely apply to the person who wants to trade on the other side of the invisible line known as a national border. If the arguments for restricted trade apply to the American economy, then surely they apply to the other nation’s economy. Logic and ethics do not change just because we cross an invisible judicial line. I take this position because I want the pro-tariff person to face the implications of his position.

It never ceases to amaze me that I am almost never able to persuade a person who defends tariffs to follow the logic of his argument. Without exception, the person insists that the invisible line dividing two jurisdictions called nations is economically significant, and therefore sales taxes on imported goods on the American side of the border are legitimate, wise, and beneficial to the vast majority of Americans. Yet, when I ask him to make exactly the same case with respect to the people on the other side of the border, which means either Canadians or Mexicans, the person has enormous difficulty in making his case. What seems utterly clear to him with respect to Americans on their side of the border seems ridiculous when he tries to state the case from the point of view of the Mexican or the Canadian on the other side of the border.

Why is this? Why is it that an argument that sounds utterly logical and utterly ethical from the point of view of an American who defends American tariffs on imported goods should not feel equally logical and equally ethical from the point of view of the Mexican or Canadian on the other side of the border?

There is a reason for this. His argument is ludicrous. When he applies it to people across the border, the argument becomes far more obviously ludicrous. So, he prefers not to consider what happens on the other side of the border.

I’ll type this very slow so that Mr. North can understand it because the argument isn’t ludicrous at all. National interests diverge. Nations compete. At times their interests run in parallel, at other times they are in direct opposition. It is in the American national interest that Americans prosper. It may or may not be in the American national interest that Mexico, China, or Russia prosper. Logic and ethics do not change depending upon the judicial line, but the objective pursued does. Just as it is not intrinsically unethical for an American to act in accordance with the American national interest, it is not automatically unethical for the Mexican to act in accordance with the interest of the Mexican people, even when both actions happen to oppose each other.

This really isn’t difficult to understand. The Minnesota Vikings and the Green Bay Packers play by the same rules of the game, and yet the Vikings’ objective is to get the football in the Green Bay end zone and the Packers’ objective is to keep it out. No one claims it is unethical for the Vikings to attempt to score or for the Packers to attempt to keep them from scoring. If we apply North’s hapless reasoning to NFL football instead of international trade, we’d have to conclude that both teams are acting illogically and unethically by simply playing the game.

North appears to be confusing the anti-free trade argument with the fair trade argument, which accepts free trade doctrine but argues it should only be applied on a reciprocal basis. I should be very curious to see Mr. North identify these “protectionist for me, but not for three” folks. I’ve certainly never read Ian Fletcher write anything about this unbalanced and hypocritical doctrine nor does it describe my own anti-free trade position.

Furthermore, I note that North isn’t discussing economics anymore, but the ethics and morality of free trade. But if we’re going to discuss the ethics and morality of free trade instead the economics, then it is necessary to consider whether it is moral for an American to place his own interests above every other American’s, and if it is ethical for a Mexican to place higher priority on the prosperity of the people of Peru above the prosperity of the people of Mexico. Is it right for Mr. North to starve his children in order to feed the children of Chile? Does he have no more responsibility to his relatives or to his neighbors than to the people of Argentina or Andorra?

And would it truly have been in the interests of either the American or the Russian people, or interests of the many nations under the Soviet heel, for the USA to prop up the Soviet economy through free trade? And if Mr. North is going to claim that there are no legitimate national interests or barriers to trade, does he understand that necessitates free international trade in plutonium, the smallpox virus, and armed drones, as well as granting green cards to as many members of the Red Army that China wishes to transport to the United States?

The foolish utopianism of North and his kind is usefully revealed in terms such as “the invisible line known as a national border”. The significant line isn’t geography, but rather people, and when the lines are not drawn in accordance with the population, trouble begins. Germany unified despite being divided into two different states because the Germans are one nation. Yugoslavia and Czechoslovakia broke up because multiple nations were trapped together in one state. The European Union was founded on the principles North espouses and it is foundering because it refused to take those “invisible lines” into account. Nations are more than mere jurisdictions.

The observable fact is that if you scratch a free trader, you reveal the globalist underneath. And since there is no greater risk to human freedom than that posed by a central global state, they are working to bring about precisely that which they fear most. And in their myopic disregard for nations, societies, and civilization, they reveal themselves to be barbarians as well.

North’s perspective isn’t so much wrong as it is simple and short-sighted. After a decade of the disastrous Bush wars, most sensible people now understand that it is not in America’s interest nor is it America’s responsibility to police the world or bring democracy to the world. North’s objective is even more problematic, as he wants America to enrich the world at the expense of the American people.

One reason the free trade doctrine is so inherently untrustworthy is that its supporters reliably fail to understand that they are presenting various aspects of multiple different arguments as if they were one coherent case, which they quite clearly are not. Moreover, North is simply lying – yes, I am accusing him outright of lying – when he writes: “The difference between the defender of tariffs and the defender of market liberty is this: the defender of tariffs does not believe, nor does he go public, with a systematic defense of the legitimacy of tariffs on the other side of the border. What he wants is a no-tariff situation on the other side of the border, and a tariff law on this side of the border. He wants Americans to be able to sell whatever they want at the best possible price to people on the other side of the border. But he does not want to have people on the other side of the border to be legally allowed to sell at the best possible price for people on this side of the border.”

I am calling Mr. North out on this blatant lie and shameless misrepresentation of those advocating barriers to international trade. It is completely and blatantly false. I do believe, and I am quite willing to go public with a systematic defense of the legitimacy of tariffs on both sides of every international border. Every nation has the right to defend its own interests as its people see fit. The same logic in defense of American interests applies to the defense of Mexican, Canadian, and Chinese interests. Other nations have the same right, and indeed, the same responsibility, to utilize tariffs to protect their native industries and domestic markets. Now, due to the smaller size of many nations, logic may dictate that their tariff laws be different than the USA’s; there is no sense in protecting jobs that don’t exist in nonexistent industries, after all. But that doesn’t change the fact that North’s accusation is completely false.


Free Trade and Gary North

In which Gary North takes on “A Tax-Loving ‘Austrian Economist'” at Lew Rockwell:

I had never heard of the individual who runs it. I looked him up. He has written a book on the coming depression. He has written another book on an unrelated topic. He has not written anything in book form on economic theory. He does not have an academic position anywhere. His academic background is limited to a bachelor’s degree in economics. College courses in economics are Keynesian. A person needs follow-up work in economics to equip himself in the field.

There is an old rule: “You cannot change just one thing.” There is a rule of economics: “If you claim to make a breakthrough in a narrow area of economics, this is going to force you to re-think almost everything else in economics.” It is not good enough to tell everybody that you have refuted the fundamental doctrine of modern free-market economics: the doctrine of free trade. You also must show that you have restructured all of economic theory in terms of your revolutionary breakthrough: discovering why sales taxes on imported goods make society richer. The site’s editor has not done this. I will go further than this: he has his work cut out for him.

It’s apparent that Mr. North has decided to labor under the decided disadvantage of arguing from ignorance. That’s a bold strategy, let’s see if it pays off for him. I’ll begin by pointing out that it is not entirely true to say I have not “not written anything in book form on economic theory” since The Return of the Great Depression not only contains a considerable amount of economic theory in it, but even suggests an minor improvement for the core mechanism of the Austrian Business Cycle to explain its greater versatility than its current mechanism would suggest. I certainly don’t have an academic position anywhere, of course, neither does Mr. North. I do have a BS in economics, which may actually be more formal economic training than Mr. North has since his PhD is in history, not economics. But does it really befit someone who appeals to the authority of Ludwig von Mises to play the academic credential game in lieu of genuine critical discourse?

Furthermore, Mr. North is blatantly wrong. While it is true that it is not enough to simply assert that one has refuted something, is absolutely unnecessary to “show that you have restructured all of economic theory in terms of your revolutionary breakthrough” in order to demonstrate that one has, in fact, successfully refuted it. Identifying the flaws in the logic that supports the doctrine or demonstrating how the logic does not, in fact, correspond to observable reality are two of the ways a doctrine can be conclusively refuted, and in fact, both of those things have been done with regards to international free trade by me and others.

In his Wiki biography, we learn that he writes science fiction novels and designs video games. I would have hoped that he had expressed greater interest in Austrian economic theory than in science fiction and video games. He claims to be an Austrian school economist. He also is in favor of tariffs. He actually admits that by promoting tariffs (sales taxes on imported goods) in the name of Austrian economic theory, his position is “apparently oxymoronic.” I recommend that he drop the adjective “apparently.”

Yeah, not so much. You don’t max level in CoD:MW2, WoW, and BF3 by reading Mises. And 750-page epic fantasies don’t write themselves while you’re mooning over your posters of Böhm-Bawerk and Rothbard. But skill as an elite sniper or battleground commander doesn’t say anything about the correctness or incorrectness of one’s economic analysis; after all, my predictive track record appears to be rather better than Mr. North’s. I find Mr. North’s lack of curiosity to be lamentable here. Since I clearly recognize the way in which it appears to be oxymoronic to suggest an Austrian defense of tariffs can be made, one would think that anyone who understands Austrian economic theory would wonder what could be the basis for such a seemingly outlandish claim. But Mr. North clearly doesn’t want to look beyond the superficial and obvious, which may explain why he is still clinging to outdated and refuted classical doctrines despite there being numerous serious critiques and literally hundreds of years of evidence to the contrary.

He began his refutation of my defense of free trade by saying that I had invoked the names of Adam Smith and David Hume. He then went on to say that he has refuted both of them – he, plus a another guy, a man who says that Ron Paul is disingenuous on free trade, a man who is on the payroll of a industry trade association that promotes protective tariffs.

Sadly, I missed these refutations. If true, a lot of fat volumes on the history of economic thought will have to be revised. Poor old Hume. Poor old Smith. Refuted at last!

Needless to say, I remain skeptical.

He then went on to say that free traders do not pay any attention to economic history. We do not understand how economic theory applies to the real world.

Here is a man who claims to be an Austrian school economist. Yet he begins by saying that economic theory does not stand alone; economic history refutes it. He is clearly arguing that economic theory is refuted, not by better economic theory, but by economic history. This is a rejection of the first hundred pages of Ludwig von Mises’ magnum opus, Human Action.

I think it is generally a good idea that when you announce your position as an Austrian school economist, you do not abandon the epistemology of Ludwig von Mises without at least explaining on what basis you have abandoned it.

The point that Mises made was simple enough: without economic theory to guide you in your selection of facts, and also in your explanation of the relevance of these facts, you cannot say anything relevant about economic history. You will be using some unstated economic theory to select and interpret the facts, except that you will be doing this either unconsciously or surreptitiously. There is no such thing as uninterpreted facts of economic history, according to Mises, and therefore the relevance of economic history must be assessed in terms of the accuracy of the theory. This is why Mises was a deductive theorist. He made this the foundational principle of his economic system.

It is true that I and others have refuted various things written by David Hume and Adam Smith. I should have mentioned David Ricardo too. Mr. North gets off to a bad start by first engaging in the genetic fallacy in order to illegitimately attempt to discredit Ian Fletcher and follows it up by admitting that he has not read any of our refutations. He then appeals to authority by pointing out that if we’re right, a good deal of revision is in order. So, right from the gate we have an argument from ignorance involving one logical fallacy followed by two appeals to authority. While Mr. North has the right to be skeptical, he does not have the right to commit three logical fallacies in a misguided attempt to justify his ignorant skepticism.

Since he is unfamiliar with my argument, Mr. North fails to grasp that I am not merely saying economic history refutes the economic theory of free trade, I am saying that the theory of free trade is theoretically flawed and economic history helps illustrate those flaws. I am suggesting various corrections to the theory, which should then bring it in line with economic history as well as permitting it to serve as a functional predictive model as it has not in the past. Furthermore, I note that there are legitimate non-economic reasons to reject free trade as public policy, although these reasons cannot properly be considered flaws in the economic doctrine itself.

Because he is arguing from ignorance, Mr. North fails to understand that I am not abandoning Misean epistemology, but rather, asserting that it has been applied improperly in the past by Mises and others. In fact, I have been intending to go through one of Mises’s pieces on free trade in much the same manner that I critically analyzed Henry Hazlitt’s chapter on the subject; clearly I should try to get around to it sooner rather than later.

My critic then said that free traders adopt arguments that are 200 years old. He is correct.

One of the important aspects of truth is this: it survives for over 200 years. Amazing as it sounds, it survives for over 2000 years. One of the characteristics of truth is that it survives through time.

Then he went into a diatribe against the European Union as fascist, something that I certainly would not argue against. The fact that the European Union is fascistic has nothing to do with the truth or falsity of the logic of voluntary exchange.

We must also consider the effects of a government agent with a gun and a badge who threatens someone who wants to work out an exchange with somebody else. The logic of badges and guns extends even earlier than Adam Smith and David Hume, and it will extend a good deal longer than my life expectancy.

He never did reply to my presentation of badges and guns. There is a reason for this. He can’t – not and still maintain the illusion that he is an Austrian school economist. There is nothing remotely Austrian about his analysis.

The problem isn’t that the arguments are 200 years old, the problem is that they haven’t been improved any in 200 years despite the growing number of theoretical criticisms and increasing amount of evidence of their failure as predictive models. The point, that Mr. North appears to have missed, is that the arguments have not survived through time. The continued belief of people who cling to those arguments and believe them to be true, while refusing to familiarize themselves with any of the counter-arguments, is not a characteristic of truth or intellectual credibility.

While the fascism of the European Union doesn’t discredit the economic doctrine of free trade itself, it does discredit it as guiding principle of public policy. The European Union was founded and justified on the doctrine of free trade and it has delivered on many of the principles of that doctrine, including the free movement of labor, the free movement of capital, and the elimination of many tariffs. And yet, the prosperity it purported to deliver has revealed itself to be a mirage and the benefits it has delivered have come at a truly hideous cost.

I paid no attention to his “presentation of badges and guns” because it is wholly irrelevant to either the theoretical flaws in the economic doctrine or the observable failure of the doctrine as a predictive model. North is using them as some sort of negative magic talisman that he can wave to automatically refute anything he dislikes, but he cannot legitimately bring “badges and guns” into the equation without also bringing in every other non-economic aspect of public policy as well, such as immigration, crime, cultural heterodoxy, religion, and moral philosophy.

As for the idea that there is nothing remotely Austrian about my analysis, I find it remarkable that North can’t see the link to Austrian theory in a criticism that is based, in part, upon the connection between trade deficits and the debt they necessarily incur.

Then he offered a paragraph on trade with South Korea. It turns out that, because of a new trade agreement that lowers tariffs from South Korea, Americans bought more goods from South Korea. Let’s see if I understand this. When you lower the price of goods, more of them are sold. Yes, yes, I think this is correct. Americans bought more goods from South Korea than we sold to them. So – I think this is right – they lent dollars to America. Does this mean “you don’t get something for nothing”? I suppose it does.

He expects hos readers to conclude:. “We must have more badges and guns and sales taxes! Nothing else will save us from poverty! Free trade, meaning free markets, meaning individual liberty of choice will destroy America otherwise! Tax us! Please tax us! We just can’t stop ourselves!”

My conceptual problem here is in understanding how a man with a badge and a gun and a sales tax would have made Americans better off. Or South Koreans.

Then he said that NAFTA is bad. Since I have never written anything in favor of NAFTA, I certainly do not want to refute him on this point. My argument related to people making an exchange, and also to a third person with a badge and a gun who sticks the gun in the belly of one of the people who wants to make an exchange, and demands payment of a sales tax. As far as I can see, this has nothing to do with NAFTA, which is a bureaucratic system for enforcing managed trade.

Mr. North first managed to be unclear about the paragraph I “offered”, which was not something I wrote but a quote from Pat Buchanan’s recent column on free trade and South Korea. Second, he failed to note that despite the price of American goods being lowered, fewer were sold to South Korea. Third, he did not address the failure of the free trade-based predictions of the Office of the U.S. Trade Representative, as the statistical evidence by which those predictions must be judged showed U.S. exporters sold fewer made-in-America goods, services and agricultural products to Korean customers and therefore did the precise opposite of supporting “more good jobs here at home”. Does this mean “you don’t get something for nothing”? No, the failure of the trade office predictions means that either the predictive model based on the free trade doctrine was applied improperly or that the model itself is incorrect.

North repeatedly fails to understand that if one makes predictions utilizing certain assumptions and those predictions are incorrect, that is an indication that the assumptions are probably incorrect and need to be revisited. And the sounder the logic involved in the argument, the more likely it is that the foundational postulates themselves are false.

To address North’s conceptual problem, a man with a badge and a gun and a sales tax would not have made South Koreans better off. They have done very handsomely out of the new free trade deal. But he could have prevented Americans from finding themselves worse off, as the US is now selling $444 million less to South Korea while adding another $825 billion in new debt. Would Mr. North would consider himself to be similarly better off if his salary were to be cut by 12 percent while he tacked on another 15% to the amount already owed on his credit card? Taking Mr. North’s logic to the extreme, we would have to conclude that being unemployed with a maxed-out credit card is the ideal economic state.

Mr. North engages in another logical fallacy, this time the No True Scotsman, when he claims that NAFTA is nothing but a a bureaucratic system for enforcing managed trade. That is partially true, but North evades the undeniable fact that NAFTA is also a partial application of free trade doctrine, as it certainly freed up the international movement of capital and labor, and reduced many tariffs as well, and failed as a predictive model in very much the same way that the South Korean trade agreement failed.

If the free trade doctrine is correct, even partial applications should partially deliver upon its promises. But the economic history that Mr. North so strangely disdains repeatedly shows that they do nothing of the sort, but rather, usually play out precisely as predicted by the policy opponents who are critics of free trade doctrine.

Then he invoked Pat Buchanan. He said that Pat had – how can I put this euphemistically? – booted my donkey. Brutally. On a website which claims to be Austrian in perspective, invoking Pat Buchanan’s authority on this issue seems to be an inappropriate source of refutation. I do not recall that Mr. Buchanan has ever identified himself as an Austrian school economist.

He also referred to the fact that I had cited Henry Hazlitt. He went on to say that Henry Hazlitt offered a remarkably incompetent argument for free trade. He insisted that he personally discovered 13 specific errors in Hazlitt’s chapter on free trade.

Let me say at this point that I find all this delightfully amusing. Anybody who says in public that he has refuted any of Henry Hazlitt’s positions with 13 different arguments is not someone I would regard as an unimpeachable source on his own powers of reasoning. Call me narrow-minded. Call me prejudiced. But that is the way I assess it.

If you read the sections which he cited from Economics in One Lesson, you may sense that you have encountered this line of reasoning before. If you have read Mises’ Human Action, Chaptrer XXIX, Section 3, then you have indeed encountered this line of reasoning before. Hazlitt merely extended Mises’ arguments, although he wrote his book several years before Human Action was published. It would be legitimate to argue that Mises extended Hazlitt’s arguments. Of course, they were both extending arguments advanced by Hume and Smith, as well as subsequent free traders. So, what our would-be Austrian economist had argued is this: to be a well-informed Austrian economist on the issue of tariffs, you should begin with a rejection of Human Action.

Once again, Mr. North resorts to the genetic fallacy. And since, unlike Mr. North, I do not engage in the logical fallacy of appeals to authority, I will point out that at no point was I appealing to Mr. Buchanan’s authority as an Austrian school economist or anything else. I was simply quoting Mr. Buchanan’s very effective point that the trade office predictions concerning South Korea based on free trade doctrine had clearly failed, as America not only increased its trade deficit, but was actually exporting less to South Korea than before.

I wouldn’t call Mr. North narrow-minded or prejudiced, simply ignorant for failing to examine the 13 Hazlittian errors I identified and foolish for thinking he could get away with such intellectually lazy behavior without getting nailed for it. Anyone who doubts my claim is certainly welcome to examine the two posts identifying the first seven errors and the second six committed by Henry Hazlitt in Chapter 11 of his useful, but outdated Economics in One Lesson. They can even read one free trader’s attempt to defend Hazlitt from some of my criticisms. Mr. North didn’t see fit to do any of that, he simply goes on to commit another logical fallacy by appealing to Hazlitt’s authority.

As for Mises, I certainly intend to critically analyze his case for free trade as well. Rather than leap right to the source, I’m methodically working backwards and identifying each new error as it was added to the doctrine. Perhaps this will lead to an eventual rejection of Human Action, but I tend to doubt it. Mises’s masterpiece is not a Marxian monolith, every last piece of which must be blindly accepted on faith lest it all collapse in complete disarray.

He then went on to say that the classical economic defense of free trade, the conventional defense of free trade, and the neo-Keynesian case for government intervention all have failed to take debt into account.

Then he presented statistics regarding America’s debts to foreigners. It seems that owing fiat money issued by the Federal Reserve System at 0.09% per annum (T-bills) is a disaster for Americans, and getting the use of goods produced abroad is an even bigger disaster. “Heads, they win; tails, we lose.” It’s a lose-lose transaction. Sadly, Americans do not understand this. For those of us who think the U.S. government will default on this debt, we look at a Hyundai and think, “This is a good deal. They get T-bills. I get the car.”

Here is reality, according to economics. Every exchange that is not completed involves debt. That is to say, it involves the use of credit. It involves the exchange of a promise to supply future goods in exchange for present goods.

Let’s consider a common transaction. I buy a house. I borrow the money to buy the house. I am now in debt inside my house. This does not mean that I am less wealthy. In fact, from my point of view, I am more wealthy. That is why I bought the house. I regard the house as more valuable to me than the present value (discounted by the mortgage rate) of the future stream of income that I will use to pay off the house.

He said that prosperity which is generated by free trade is a mirage. He did not bother to prove this. It really does need proof. Why is the subjective value that someone gets from owning something a mirage? Why are the benefits of trade with someone across the street or across town a mirage? How about across state lines? What’s that? It’s not a mirage? But it is when I buy something across a national line, unless I get to pay a sales tax.

The logic of his position is not intuitive. It needs an explanation. But my critic did not provide one.

I buy things online. I do not pay a local sales tax. Is this increase of my subjective wealth a mirage? Would I be better off economically if I had bought it locally and paid a state and county sales tax? Are all of us who buy online victims of a mirage? This is the logic of his position. But his argument is not supported by logic. It is supported by lots of numbers issued by government statistical agencies. The numbers show that we online shoppers are suffering from the mirage of wealth. He understands this. I do not. Do you?

By attempting to justify free trade by appealing to the possibility of paying for a car with defaulted T-bills, Mr. North is advocating outright theft. This is monstrous, particularly for one who keeps making to the non-economic “badges and guns” argument. And note that North goes so far to claim that being in mortgage debt makes one intrinsically more wealthy, which is a spectacularly bizarre argument for someone questioning my Austrian allegiances to make. Furthermore, I did prove that the prosperity supposedly produced by free trade, which is customarily measured in GDP growth, is a mirage, because I showed that the debt/GDP per capita ratio has increased dramatically from 1960 to the present. While one can shift the argument from GDP to household assets, that doesn’t change the fact that the debt figures demonstrate that the GDP-based argument for free trade is an illusory one.

His online consumer analogy fails by Austrian standards because he is confusing internal free trade with trans-national free trade. The two are not synonymous due to the relative immobility of capital and labor across international borders, as Mises himself noted.

“The sole justification for distinguishing in economic theory between domestic and foreign trade is to be found in the fact that in the case of the former there is free mobility of capital and labor, whereas this is not true in regard to the commerce between nations.”

This does bring us to one of the non-economic aspects of the matter, but suffice it to say that unless Mr. North is as to pursue his occupation in Bangladesh or Mongolia as he is to move it to Florida or Arizona, he cannot reasonably make use of domestic analogies in order to defend international free trade. Indeed, this goes to the very heart of the matter, and the fact that many free trade advocates have gone so far as to dishonestly attempt to claim that the free movement of labor is not an intrinsic aspect of free trade is evidence that even some of free trade’s more vehement supporters are beginning to realize some of the fundamental flaws of the doctrine.

To overcome this mirage, we need tariffs, he implied. In other words, when two people get together to make an exchange, and somebody with a badge and a gun does not stick his gun into the belly of one of the individuals to demand payment of the sales tax, this absence of guns and badges and the threat of violence decreases their prosperity. So, there is nothing like a badge and a gun in your belly, coupled with the demand that you pay a sales tax, to make you richer.

Think of the possibilities here. If there were another guy with a badge who sticks a gun in your back, and he demands that you pay an additional sales tax, you could get rich really fast.

This is the logic of every defense of tariffs that is not made exclusively in terms of financing the government. Any argument for tariffs that says that there is a benefit to society in general from sending out people with badges and guns to collect sales taxes, is a defense of badges and guns and sales taxes as crucial tools of production.

Historically and theoretically, Austrian school economists have not been prominent in promoting the idea that badges, guns, and higher sales taxes promote greater social welfare.

He said that the logic of free trade was always erroneous, because any consideration of debt which is put into the equation – he never did provide an equation – reveals from historical statistics the intrinsic falsity of the free-trade argument.

Mr. North is simply engaging in silly rhetoric here, meant to appeal to those Aristotle described as being incapable of education through dialectic. His appeal to badges and guns has nothing whatsoever to do with economic theory, and more to the point, is a terrible analogy since it leaves out the way each exchange reduces one party’s ability to engage in future exchanges. And it is amusing that he tries to assert I am claiming badges and guns and sales taxes are crucial tools of production when if we follow his free trade logic to its extreme, it should be obvious that there will be no production taking place except where the capital and labor all flows to their ideal location for maximum efficiency.

He also mischaracterizes what I wrote, as he invents a link between the erroneous logic of free trade and the way in which the debt statistics disprove the empirical case for free trade. Not the logical one; the logic fails on its own terms. Mr. North clearly doesn’t understand the differences between the theoretical case, the empirical case, and the moral case as he keeps mixing them up.

He specifically said that buying giant houses with no money down did not make people richer. Well, how about buying smaller houses with no money down? Did that make people poorer? A lot of people over the last 75 years have bought homes for 20% down, which certainly involved debt. Did that make them less rich? Did that impoverish them?

I realize that people can make bad decisions. That possibility is basic to all economic thought, but especially Austrian economic thought. People make bad decisions based on faulty information. Fractional reserve banking and central banking are sources of widespread false information. This perspective is basic to Austrian school economics. But the fact that people were misled by fractional reserve banking and central banking does not prove that they would have been better off if somebody with a badge and a gun had charged them an extra 5% or 10% sales tax.

This supposed Austrian school economist, who has never written anything on Austrian economic international trade theory in book form, and who claims that he has refuted 13 of Henry Hazlitt’s arguments, and who has refuted David Hume and Adam Smith, is persuaded that people who pursue their individual self-interest according to the best information they have are really fools. They do not have good information. But he thinks he does. And so, this Austrian school economist wants the federal government to send out people with badges and guns to demand sales taxes from buyers, so that Americans who want to make exchanges will be less likely to do so. This will reduce their victimization by the mirage of wealth.

Taxation produces liberty. Taxation produces wealth. Taxation reduces mirages. Taxation clears the mind. Ingsoc was right, it seems.

More rhetoric and posturing. It is little wonder that he didn’t understand the link between the housing boom and the financial crisis. But it is no harder to understand that taxation can, in some circumstances, produce liberty and wealth than to grasp the equally difficult notion that raising tax rates does not always increase tax revenue. Mr. North appears to have a very simplistic mind that does not understand complex relationships that are more than simple ratios.

Let me push this logic. If all this is true of trade between people across the invisible borders separating nations, then it must be logically true regarding the invisible borders separating states inside the United States. It must also be true with respect to invisible borders separating counties.

Therefore, in order to make everybody richer, each of these government jurisdictions should send out men with badges and guns to interdict the shipment of goods across those invisible lines. They must all impose sales taxes. Why? Because, if this is not done, society will become poorer. It will succumb to the mirage of wealth.

CONCLUSION

All this comes from a guy who says he is a member of Mensa, an organization of geniuses. This reminds me, once again, that if a buzz saw is set at the wrong angle, you can sharpen it for hours, but it will not cut straight.

Mr. North here reveals both his logical incompetence as well as demonstrating his insufficient knowledge of Mises. As I already pointed out, the free mobility of capital and labor inside the United States fundamentally distinguishes internal trade from international trade.


Gary North responds, in a way

There are times when I wonder if MPAI truly is a reasonable philosophy for preparing oneself for the quotidian burden of dealing with others. And then I read something like this pathetic handwaving on the part of Gary North, which purports to be a defense of free trade in response to my suggestion that there may be an Austrian case against free trade:

Here is the inescapable reality: if you do not understand the argument, you probably will not understand the refutation. You will not really know if the refutation effectively refutes the original argument. You are not really concerned about the logic of the argument. You are concerned about the fact that somebody you have never heard of thinks you are wrong, but you do not know why you are wrong. So, you want to find somebody you trust who will prove to you, merely by saying “this argument is wrong,” that this argument is wrong. This is a lose-lose position. You lose because you do not understand the original argument, and you lose because you do not understand the refutation either. It is best to ignore the argument. Anyway, it certainly is cheaper.

My subscriber had come across a website. The site is a blog. I had never heard of the individual who runs it. I looked him up. He has written a book on the coming depression. He has written another book on an unrelated topic. He has not written anything in book form on economic theory. He does not have an academic position anywhere. His academic background is limited to a bachelor’s degree in economics. College courses in economics are Keynesian. A person needs follow-up work in economics to equip himself in the field.

There is an old rule: “You cannot change just one thing.” There is a rule of economics: “If you claim to make a breakthrough in a narrow area of economics, this is going to force you to re-think almost everything else in economics.” It is not good enough to tell everybody that you have refuted the fundamental doctrine of modern free-market economics: the doctrine of free trade. You also must show that you have restructured all of economic theory in terms of your revolutionary breakthrough: discovering why sales taxes on imported goods make society richer. The site’s editor has not done this. I will go further than this: he has his work cut out for him.

I’ll do my usual number on North’s post either tomorrow or later today, but it reminds me of my disappointment when Thomas Sowell feebly attempted to defend Michelle Malkin’s shoddy and ludicrously ignorant defense of internment even after I pointed out her easily confirmed factual errors. If I ever get so intellectually calcified and unable to respond substantively to material arguments, I hope I have sufficient self-respect to give up writing commentary and find some other means of entertaining myself.

Anyhow, before I begin writing my critique of his response, I’m curious to know how many of you, free traders or not, genuinely find this response to be a convincing one. North isn’t an idiot, and while I’ve never been a particular fan of his, my father and brother are, and I’ve read enough of his pieces in the past to know that whatever this is, it is not his fastball. So, has he lost it, is he phoning it in, or am I simply missing his subtle brilliance in methodically demolishing the case against free trade?

I’m not in the least bit put out that North hasn’t heard of me. I tend to doubt he was a big Wax Trax! aficionado. But even if he had, what, I wonder, would that have to do with the net effect of free trade on the US economy?


An Austrian case against free trade

Not long ago, Gary North wrote a column with some rather incendiary claims entitled “Free Trade: The Litmus Test of Economics“. In it, he relied on the 18th century arguments of David Hume and Adam Smith, both of which have been refuted by me, Ian Fletcher, and numerous other skeptics of free trade. Is our skepticism based on what North calls “trust in state power”? Is it really “faith in the economic productivity of men with badges and guns”?

Of course not. One of the interesting things about myopic free traders like North is that they stubbornly refuse to pay any attention to economic history or the observable consequences of their logic when it is tested by real world application. This is why they are constantly retreating to oft-refuted arguments that are more than 200 years old rather than attempting to defend their position on the basis of the post-NAFTA performance of the US economy or the economic state of the European common market now known as the European Union.

As an aside, I note that the European Union is one of the most fascistic, illiberal, intrusive, and centralized state powers in the world and it was largely constructed upon free trade-based arguments. Contrast North’s superficial and outdated polemic with Pat Buchanan’s WND column today which observes some very recent results of the latest experiment in free trade.

“The entry into force of the U.S.-Korea trade agreement on March 15, 2012, means countless new opportunities for U.S. exporters to sell more made-in-America goods, services and agricultural products to Korean customers – and to support more good jobs here at home.”

Thus did the Office of the U.S. Trade Representative rhapsodize about the potential of our new trade treaty with South Korea. And how has it worked out for Uncle Sam? Well, courtesy of Martin Crutsinger of the Associated Press, the trade figures are in for April, the first full month under the trade deal with South Korea.

And, surprise! The U.S. trade deficit with Korea tripled in one month. Imports from South Korea jumped 15 percent to $5.5 billion in April, while U.S. exports to South Korea fell 12 percent to $3.7 billion. Suddenly, the U.S. trade deficit with Seoul surged to an annual rate of $22 billion.

Shades of NAFTA. When it passed in 1993, we had a $1.6 billion trade surplus with Mexico. By 2010, our trade deficit with Mexico had reached $61.6 billion.

Verdict: Buchanan brutally kicks North’s ass. North’s only response to this would be to celebrate the growing trade deficit because “the world is richer than it was in 1973”. Regardless of whether that is true or not, the more relevant fact is that the United States of America is considerably poorer than it was in 1973, with lower wages, higher unemployment, and reduced net wealth. While there is no question that North’s ideological heart is in the right place, his intellectual limitations in the field of economics become readily apparent when one sees how he praises Henry Hazlitt’s hapless attempt to justify free trade:

“Henry Hazlitt’s classic little book, Economics in One Lesson, so completely destroys the arguments of the tariff supporters that there is nothing left of their position; still they keep coming. For two centuries their position has been intellectually bankrupt; still they keep coming.”

I found this statement more than a little amusing, of course, because it was trivially easy to show how Hazlitt’s book not only fails to completely destroy the anti-free trade case, but is a remarkably incompetent argument when examined in detail. I say this because I identified no less than 13 specific errors in his chapter on free trade in the first and second parts of the Hazlitt International Trade Challenge. Like most conventional – if not mainstream – economists, North is handicapped by his failure to pay any attention to debt. The following pair of charts show why North and other free traders feel their position is supported by the macroeconomic statistics, then show why their position is absolutely and utterly untenable.

This chart shows the free trade case. Since 1960, the trade deficit has gone from +3.5 billion to -494.7 billion while GDP/Capita has grown from $2,935.49 to $47,790.09. The growth in GDP has increased much faster than the population growth, therefore it appears to be obvious that the trade deficit is not only making the world richer, it is making the United States richer. However, this does not tell the entire story. As I mentioned previously, both the classical and the conventional free trade cases, like the Neo-Keynesian case for government intervention, completely fail to take debt into account.

Notice how adding the overall debt level of the economy completely changes the picture and makes it obvious how the trade deficit is impoverishing the USA despite the increase in GDP. GDP that does not account for debt is a terrible measure of wealth and every bit as misleading as GDP that does not account for inflation, as it is nothing more than a metric intended to track national income. Whereas per capita wealth, measured by GDP/capita – debt/capita was only -$1,417 in 1960, it has increased by two orders of magnitude to -$120,014. Debt that could once be paid off in 17 months would now require 42 months.

The prosperity that North and others claim free trade has brought the USA is nothing but a mirage and is the simple result of Americans borrowing to buy those foreign goods and services with money they will have to pay back from a smaller industrial base competing against much more serious competitors than they faced 50 years ago.

The case for free trade was always logically flawed, and on the empirical level simply cannot survive the incorporation of debt into the equation, as the historical statistics clearly demonstrate the intrinsic falsity that was always apparent to the sufficiently careful economic analyst. Free trade has not made the USA more wealthy, any more than buying giant houses with no-money down mortgages during the housing boom made those individuals who bought them rich. It hardly amounts to “state worship” to note that debt is not wealth. And it should be clear that by depriving the local consumers of their jobs and their ability to pay for imported goods and services, free trade necessarily requires either a decline in living standards or a constantly increasing debt load for countries on the red side of the trade deficit.

An so, as strange as it may sound, this observation points towards the legitimate possibility of developing the apparently oxymoronic Austrian case against free trade.